Essay/Term paper: Macbeth
Essay, term paper, research paper: Macbeth
Free essays available online are good but they will not follow the guidelines of your particular writing assignment. If you need a custom term paper on Macbeth: Macbeth, you can hire a professional writer here to write you a high quality authentic essay. While free essays can be traced by Turnitin (plagiarism detection program), our custom written essays will pass any plagiarism test. Our writing service will save you time and grade.
MACBETH
Macbeth is presented as a mature man of definitely established character, successful
in certain fields of activity and enjoying an enviable reputation. We must not conclude,
there, that all his volitions and actions are predictable; Macbeth's character, like any
other man's at a given moment, is what is being made out of potentialities plus
environment, and no one, not even Macbeth himself, can know all his inordinate self-
love whose actions are discovered to be-and no doubt have been for a long time-
determined mainly by an inordinate desire for some temporal or mutable good.
Macbeth is actuated in his conduct mainly by an inordinate desire for worldly honors;
his delight lies primarily in buying golden opinions from all sorts of people. But we must
not, therefore, deny him an entirely human complexity of motives. For example, his
fighting in Duncan's service is magnificent and courageous, and his evident joy in
it is traceable in art to the natural pleasure which accompanies the explosive expenditure
of prodigious physical energy and the euphoria which follows. He also rejoices no
doubt in the success which crowns his efforts in battle - and so on. He may even
conceived of the proper motive which should energize back of his great deed:
The service and the loyalty I owe,
In doing it, pays itself.
But while he destroys the king's enemies, such motives work but dimly at best and are
obscured in his consciousness by more vigorous urges. In the main, as we have said, his
nature violently demands rewards: he fights valiantly in order that he may be reported in
such terms a "valour's minion" and "Bellona's bridegroom"' he values success because it
brings spectacular fame and new titles and royal favor heaped upon him in public. Now
so long as these mutable goods are at all commensurate with his inordinate desires - and
such is the case, up until he covets the kingship - Macbeth remains an honorable
gentleman. He is not a criminal; he has no criminal tendencies. But once permit his self-
love to demand a satisfaction which cannot be honorably attained, and he is likely to
grasp any dishonorable means to that end which may be safely employed. In other words,
Macbeth has much of natural good in him unimpaired; environment has conspired with
his nature to make him upright in all his dealings with those about him. But moral
goodness in him is undeveloped and indeed still rudimentary, for his voluntary acts are
scarcely brought into harmony with ultimate end. As he returns from victorious battle,
puffed up with self-love which demands ever-increasing recognition of his greatness, the
demonic forces of evil-symbolized by the Weird Sisters-suggest to his inordinate
imagination the splendid prospect of attaining now the greatest mutable good he has
ever desired. These demons in the guise of witches cannot read his inmost thoughts, but
from observation of facial expression and other bodily manifestations they surmise with
comparative accuracy what passions drive him and what dark desires await their
fostering. Realizing that he wishes the kingdom, they prophesy that he shall be king.
They cannot thus compel his will to evil; but they do arouse his passions and stir up a
vehement and inordinate apprehension of the imagination, which so perverts the
judgment of reason that it leads his will toward choosing means to the desired temporal
good. Indeed his imagination and passions are so vivid under this evil impulse from
without that "nothing is but what is not"; and his reason is so impeded that he judges,
"These solicitings cannot be evil, cannot be good." Still, he is provided with so much
natural good that he is able to control the apprehensions of his inordinate imagination
and decides to take no step involving crime. His autonomous decision not to commit
murder, however, is not in any sense based upon moral grounds. No doubt he normally
shrinks from the unnaturalness of regicide; but he so far ignores ultimate ends that, if he
could perform the deed and escape its consequences here upon this bank and shoal of
time, he'ld jump the life to come. Without denying him still a complexity of motives - as
kinsman and subject he may possibly experience some slight shade of unmixed loyalty to
the King under his roof-we may even say that the consequences which he fears are not at
all inward and spiritual, It is to be doubted whether he has ever so far considered the
possible effects of crime and evil upon the human soul-his later discovery of horrible
ravages produced by evil in his own spirit constitutes part of the tragedy. Hi is mainly
concerned, as we might expect, with consequences involving the loss of mutable goods
which he already possesses and values highly.
After the murder of Duncan, the natural good in him compels the acknowledgment
that, in committing the unnatural act, he has filed his mind and has given his eternal
jewel, the soul, into the possession of those demonic forces which are the enemy of
mankind. He recognizes that the acts of conscience which torture him are really
expressions of that outraged natural law, which inevitably reduced him as individual to
the essentially human. This is the inescapable bond that keeps him pale, and this is the
law of his own natural from whose exactions of devastating penalties he seeks release:
Come, seeling night...
And with thy bloody and invisible hand
Cancel and tear to pieces that great bond
Which keeps me pale.
He conceives that quick escape from the accusations of conscience may possibly be
effected by utter extirpation of the precepts of natural law deposited in his nature. And he
imagines that the execution of more bloody deeds will serve his purpose. Accordingly,
then, in the interest of personal safety and in order to destroy the essential humanity in
himself, he instigates the murder of Banquo.
But he gains no satisfying peace because his conscience still obliges him to recognize
the negative quality of evil and the barren results of wicked action. The individual who
once prized mutable goods in the form of respect and admiration from those about him,
now discovers that even such evanescent satisfactions are denied him:
And that which should accompany old age,
As honor, love, obedience, troops of friends,
I must not look to have; but, in their stead,
Curses, not loud but deep, mouth-honour, breath,
Which the poor heart would fain deny, and dare not.
But the man is conscious of a profound abstraction of something far more precious that
temporal goods. His being has shrunk to such little measure that he has lost his former
sensitiveness to good and evil; he has supped so full with horrors and the disposition of
evil is so fixed in him that nothing can start him. His conscience is numbed so that he
escapes the domination of fears, and such a consummation may indeed be called a sort of
peace. But it is not entirely what expected or desires. Back of his tragic volitions is the
ineradicable urge toward that supreme contentment which accompanies and rewards
fully actuated being; the peace which he attains is psychologically a callousness to pain
and spiritually a partial insensibility to the evidences of diminished being. His peace is
the doubtful calm of utter negativity, where nothing matters.
This spectacle of spiritual deterioration carried to the point of imminent dissolution
arouses in us, however, a curious feeling of exaltation. For even after the external and
internal forces of evil have done their worst, Macbeth remains essentially human and his
conscience continues to witness the diminution of his being. That is to say, there is still
left necessarily some natural good in him; sin cannot completely deprive him of his
rational nature, which is the root of his inescapable inclination to virtue. We do not need
Hecate to tell us that he is but a wayward son, spiteful and wrathful, who, as other do,
loves for his own ends. This is apparent throughout the drama; he never sins because, like
the Weird Sisters, he loves evil for its own sake; and whatever he does is inevitably in
pursuance of some apparent good, even though that apparent good is only temporal of
nothing more that escape from a present evil. At the end, in spite of shattered nerves and
extreme distraction of mind, the individual passes out still adhering admirably to his
code of personal courage, and the man's conscience still clearly admonishes that he has
done evil.
Moreover, he never quite loses completely the liberty of free choice, which is the
supreme bonum naturae of mankind.But since a wholly free act is one in accordance with
reason, in proportion as his reason is more and more blinded by inordinate apprehension
of the imagination and passions of the sensitive appetite, his volitions become less and
less free. And this accounts for our feeling, toward the end of the drama, that his actions
are almost entirely determined and that some fatality is compelling him to his doom. This
compulsion is in no sense from without-though theologians may at will interpret it so-as
if some god, like Zeus in Greek tragedy, were dealing out punishment for the breaking of
divine law. It is generated rather from within, and it is not merely a psychological
phenomenon. Precepts of the natural law-imprints of the eternal law- deposited in his
nature have been violated, irrational acts have established habits tending to further
irrationality, and one of the penalties exacted is dire impairment of the liberty of free
choice. Thus the Fate which broods over Macbeth may be identified with that disposition
inherent in created things, in this case the fundamental motive principle of human action,
by which providence knits all things in their proper order. Macbeth cannot escape
entirely from his proper order; he must inevitably remain essentially human.
The substance of Macbeth's personality is that out of which tragic heroes are
fashioned; it is endowed by the dramatist with an astonishing abundance and variety of
potentialities. And it is upon the development of these potentialities that the artist
lavishes the full energies of his creative powers. Under the influence of swiftly altering
environment which continually furnishes or elicts new experiences and under the impact
of passions constantly shifting and mounting in intensity, the dramatic individual grows,
expands, developes to the point where, at the end of the drama, he looms upon the mind
as a titanic personality infinitely richer that at the beginning. This dramatic personality in
its manifold stages of actuation in as artistic creation. In essence Macbeth, like all other
men, is inevitably bound to his humanity; the reason of order, as we have seen,
determines his inescapable relationship to the natural and eternal law, compels
inclination toward his proper act and end but provides him with a will capable of
free choice, and obliges his discernment of good and evil.